Hall's Marriage Theorem/General Set

From ProofWiki
Jump to navigation Jump to search



Theorem

Let $\SS = \family {S_k}_{k \mathop \in I}$ be an indexed family of finite sets.

For each $F \subseteq I$, let $\ds Y_F = \bigcup_{k \mathop \in F} S_k$.

Let $Y = Y_I$.


Then the following are equivalent:

$(1): \quad \SS$ satisfies the marriage condition: for each finite subset $F \subseteq I : \card F \le \card {Y_F}$.
$(2): \quad$ There exists an injection $f: I \to Y$ such that $\forall k \in I: \map f k \in S_k$.


Proof

$(2)$ implies $(1)$

Suppose that for some finite $F \subseteq I$, $\card F > \card {Y_F}$.

Then $\card F \not \le \card {Y_F}$.

By contrapositive of Injection implies Cardinal Inequality, there can be no injection from $F$ to $Y_F$.

Thus there can be no injection from $I$ to $Y$ satisfying the requirements.

$\Box$


$(1)$ implies $(2)$

Let $\map \Phi x$ be the set of all elements of $y$ in the expression of $x$.



Let $\FF$ be the set of all partial functions $g$ from $I$ to $Y$ such that:

$g$ is one-to-one.
If $\tuple {k, y} \in g$, then $y \in S_k$.

Then for any $k \in I$, $\set {\map g x: g \in \FF \land k \in \Dom g}$ is finite.

$\FF$ has finite character:

Let $g \in \FF$.

Let $F$ be a finite subset of $I$.

Then $g \restriction F$ is obviously in $\FF$.

Suppose instead that $g$ is a partial function from $I$ to $Y$.

Let the restriction of $g$ to each finite subset of $\Dom g$ be in $\FF$.

Then $g$ is one-to-one, as follows:

Let $p, q \in \Dom g$ with $p \ne q$.

Then $\set {p, q}$ is a finite subset of $\Dom g$.

Thus:

$g \restriction \set {p, q} \in \FF$

Thus:

$\map g p \ne \map g q$

Let $\tuple {k, y} \in g$.

Then:

$\tuple {k, y} \in g \restriction \set k$

So:

$y \in S_k$

Thus:

$g \in \FF$

So we see that $\FF$ has finite character.


Let $F$ be a finite subset of $I$.

By the finite case, there is an element of $\FF$ with domain $F$.

By the Cowen-Engeler Lemma, $\FF$ has an element $\phi$ whose domain is $I$.

That is, $\phi$ is a mapping from $I$ to $Y$.

But a one-to-one mapping is an injection, so $\phi$ is an injection from $X$ to $Y$.

By the definition of $\FF$:

$\forall k \in I: \map \phi k \in S_k$

$\blacksquare$


Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem

This theorem depends on the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem (BPI), by way of Cowen-Engeler Lemma.

Although not as strong as the Axiom of Choice, the BPI is similarly independent of the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms.

As such, mathematicians are generally convinced of its truth and believe that it should be generally accepted.


Explanation

This Hall's Marriage Theorem is so called for the following reason:

Let $I$ be a set of women.

Suppose that each woman $k$ is romantically interested in a finite set $S_k$ of men.

Suppose also that:

each woman would like to marry exactly one of these men

and:

each man in $\ds \bigcup_{k \mathop \in I} S_k$ would like to marry at most one woman in $I$.

Then this theorem gives a condition under which it is possible to match every woman to a man.


Source of Name

This entry was named for Philip Hall.