Sequentially Compact Metric Space is Totally Bounded/Proof 1

From ProofWiki
Jump to navigation Jump to search

Theorem

Let $M = \struct {A, d}$ be a metric space.

Let $M$ be sequentially compact.


Then $M$ is totally bounded.


Proof

Let $\epsilon \in \R_{>0}$ be a strictly positive real number.

By definition, $M$ is totally bounded only if there exists a finite $\epsilon$-net for $M$.


Aiming for a contradiction, suppose there exists no finite $\epsilon$-net for $M$.

The aim is to construct an infinite sequence $\sequence {x_n}_{n \ge 1}$ in $A$ that has no convergent subsequence.


For all natural numbers $n \ge 1$, define the set:

$\SS_n = \set {F \subseteq A: \size F = n: \forall x, y \in F: x \ne y \implies \map d {x, y} \ge \epsilon}$

where $\size F$ denotes the cardinality of $F$.

We use the Principle of Mathematical Induction to prove that $\SS_n$ is non-empty.


It is vacuously true that any singleton $\set x \subseteq A$ is an element of $\SS_1$.

Since $A$ is non-empty by the definition of a metric space, it follows from Existence of Singleton Set that $\SS_1$ is non-empty.


Let $F \in \SS_n$.

By definition, $F$ is finite.

So $F$ is not an $\epsilon$-net for $M$, by hypothesis.

Hence, there exists an $x \in A$ such that:

$\forall y \in F: \map d {x, y} \ge \epsilon$

Note that, by Metric Space Axiom $(\text M 1)$:

$x \notin F$

Consider the set:

$F' := F \cup \set x$.

Then:

$\size {F'} = n + 1$

and by Metric Space Axiom $(\text M 3)$:

$F' \in \SS_{n + 1}$


Thus, we have proven that $\SS_n$ is non-empty for all natural numbers $n \ge 1$.


Therefore, using the axiom of countable choice, we can obtain an infinite sequence $\sequence {F_n}_{n \ge 1}$ such that:

$\forall n \in \N_{\ge 1}: F_n \in \SS_n$

From Countable Union of Countable Sets is Countable, there exists an injection:

$\ds \phi: \bigcup_{n \mathop \ge 1} F_n \to \N$


We now construct an infinite sequence $\sequence {x_n}_{n \ge 1}$ in $A$.



To do this, we use the Principle of Recursive Definition to define the sequence $\sequence {\tuple {x_1, x_2, \ldots, x_n} }_{n \ge 1}$ of ordered $n$-tuples.

Let $x_1 \in F_1$.

Suppose that $x_1, x_2, \ldots, x_n$ have been defined, and let:

$T_n = \set {x_1, x_2, \ldots, x_n}$

Define:

$D_n = \set {x \in F_{n + 1}: \forall y \in T_n: \map d {x, y} \ge \dfrac \epsilon 2}$


Using a Proof by Contradiction, we show that $D_n$ is non-empty.

For all $x \in F_{n + 1}$, define:

$\map {C_n} x = \set {y \in T_n: \map d {x, y} < \dfrac \epsilon 2}$

Let $x, x' \in F_{n + 1}$ be distinct.

Let $y \in \map {C_n} x$.

Then it follows from:

the definition of $F_{n + 1}$
Metric Space Axiom $(\text M 2)$: Triangle Inequality and Metric Space Axiom $(\text M 3)$:

that:

$\map d {x', y} \ge \map d {x, x'} - \map d {x, y} > \dfrac \epsilon 2$

Hence, $y \notin \map {C_n} {x'}$.

That is, the indexed family of sets:

$\sequence {\map {C_n} x}_{x \in F_{n + 1}}$

is pairwise disjoint.

Suppose that $D_n$ is empty.

That is:

$\forall x \in F_{n + 1}: \map {C_n} x$ is non-empty

Then, from Cardinality is Additive Function, Finite Union of Sets in Additive Function, and Cardinality of Subset of Finite Set, we have:

$\ds \size {F_{n + 1} } \le \sum_{x \mathop \in F_{n + 1} } \size {\map {C_n} x} \le \size {T_n} < \size {F_{n + 1} }$

which is a contradiction.



From the well-ordering principle, we have that $\struct {\N, \le}$ is a well-ordered set.

Let $\le_{\phi}$ be the ordering induced by $\phi$.

Then $\le_{\phi}$ is a well-ordering.

We define $x_{n + 1}$ as the (unique) $\le_{\phi}$-smallest element of $D_n$.


By construction:

$\forall m, n \in \N_{>0}: m \le n \implies \map d {x_{n + 1}, x_m} \ge \dfrac \epsilon 2$

Hence, by induction, it follows from Metric Space Axiom $(\text M 3)$ that:

$\forall m, n \in \N_{>0}: m \ne n \implies \map d {x_m, x_n} \ge \dfrac \epsilon 2$

Therefore, the sequence $\sequence {x_n}$ has no Cauchy subsequence.

From Convergent Sequence in Metric Space is Cauchy Sequence, $\sequence {x_n}$ has no convergent subsequence either.

Thus, by definition, $M$ is not sequentially compact.

But this contradicts the original assumption that $M$ is sequentially compact.

Thus the assumption that there exists no finite $\epsilon$-net for $M$ was false.

Therefore, by definition, $M$ is totally bounded.

Hence the result.

$\blacksquare$


Axiom of Countable Choice

This theorem depends on the Axiom of Countable Choice.

Although not as strong as the Axiom of Choice, the Axiom of Countable Choice is similarly independent of the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms.

As such, mathematicians are generally convinced of its truth and believe that it should be generally accepted.