Transfinite Recursion Theorem/Formulation 1

From ProofWiki
Jump to navigation Jump to search

Theorem

Let $M$ be a class.

Let $g$ be a strictly progressing mapping on $M$.

Let $M$ be minimally superinductive under $g$.

For an arbitrary ordinal $\alpha$, let $M_\alpha$ be the $\alpha$th element of $M$ under the well-ordered class $\struct {M, \subseteq}$.


Then:

\((1)\)   $:$   Zeroth Ordinal:       \(\ds M_0 \)   \(\ds = \)   \(\ds \O \)      
\((2)\)   $:$   Successor Ordinal:      \(\ds \forall \alpha \in \On:\)    \(\ds M_{\alpha^+} \)   \(\ds = \)   \(\ds \map g {M_\alpha} \)      
\((3)\)   $:$   Limit Ordinal:      \(\ds \forall \lambda \in K_{II}:\)    \(\ds M_\lambda \)   \(\ds = \)   \(\ds \bigcup_{\alpha \mathop < \lambda} M_\alpha \)      

where:

$\On$ denotes the class of all ordinals
$K_{II}$ denotes the class of all limit ordinals.


Proof 1

Let $\On$ denote the class of all ordinals.

By the Superinductive Class under Strictly Progressing Mapping is Proper Class, $M$ is not a set; it is a proper class.

From Minimally Superinductive Class is Well-Ordered under Subset Relation, $\struct {M, \subseteq}$ is indeed a well-ordered class.


By definition, $M$ is a $g$-tower.

Hence from $g$-Tower is Well-Ordered under Subset Relation:

$(1): \quad \O$ is the smallest element of $M$.
$(2): \quad$ The immediate successor of $x$ under the well-ordering $\subseteq$ is $\map g x$.
$(3): \quad$ For a limit element $x$ of $M$:
$x = \bigcup x^\subset$
where $\bigcup x^\subset$ denotes the union of the lower section of $x$.


From the Counting Theorem, there exists a unique order isomorphism from $\On$ to $M$.

Let $M_\alpha$ denote the element of $M$ corresponding to $\alpha$ under this order isomorphism.

We refer to $M_\alpha$ as the "$\alpha$th element of $M$".

By the definition of order isomorphism, it is immediate that $M_0$ is the smallest element of $M$ under the well-ordering induced by $\subseteq$.

Hence:

$M_0 = \O$

It is also immediate that $M_{\alpha^+}$ is the immediate successor of $M_\alpha$, that is:

$M_{\alpha^+} = \map g {M_\alpha}$

Let $\lambda$ be a limit ordinal.

Then $M_\lambda$ is a limit element of $M$:.

Hence $M_\lambda$ is the union of the set of all $M_\alpha$ such that $\alpha < \lambda$.

That is:

$\ds M_\lambda = \bigcup_{\alpha \mathop < \lambda} M_\alpha$

Hence the result.

$\blacksquare$


Proof 2

This is a special case of Transfinite Recursion Theorem: Formulation $4$.

Let $\On$ denote the class of all ordinals.

Let $g$ be a mapping defined for all sets.

Let $c$ be a set.


Then there exists a unique $\On$-sequence $S_0, S_1, \dots, S_\alpha, \dots$ such that:

\((1)\)   $:$      \(\ds S_0 \)   \(\ds = \)   \(\ds c \)      
\((2)\)   $:$     \(\ds \forall \alpha \in \On:\)    \(\ds S_{\alpha + 1} \)   \(\ds = \)   \(\ds \map g {S_\alpha} \)      
\((3)\)   $:$     \(\ds \forall \lambda \in K_{II}:\)    \(\ds S_\lambda \)   \(\ds = \)   \(\ds \bigcup_{\alpha \mathop < \lambda} S_\alpha \)      

where $K_{II}$ denotes the class of all limit ordinals.

$\Box$


Take $c$ to be $0$, that is $\O$.

Let us take the special case where $g$ is a strictly progressing mapping.

The result follows directly.

$\blacksquare$