Definition:Language of Set Theory
Definition
![]() | This page has been identified as a candidate for refactoring of advanced complexity. Until this has been finished, please leave {{Refactor}} in the code.
New contributors: Refactoring is a task which is expected to be undertaken by experienced editors only. Because of the underlying complexity of the work needed, it is recommended that you do not embark on a refactoring task until you have become familiar with the structural nature of pages of $\mathsf{Pr} \infty \mathsf{fWiki}$.To discuss this page in more detail, feel free to use the talk page. When this work has been completed, you may remove this instance of {{Refactor}} from the code. |
The language of set theory consists of the language of predicate logic with the binary predicate symbol $\in$, denoting membership.
Predicate Symbols
The language of set theory uses only one predicate symbol, $\in$, the membership sign.
It is a binary predicate symbol.
Using $\in$, other symbols such as $=$ can be defined (see Definition:Set Equality).
Connectives
The language of set theory borrows the connectives from the language of predicate logic. However, some of the connectives can be considered definitional abbreviations.
$\land$ and $\neg$ can be taken as primitive connectives with the following definitional abbreviations:
\(\ds P \implies Q\) | \(\operatorname{for}\) | \(\ds \neg ( P \land \neg Q )\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds P \lor Q\) | \(\operatorname{for}\) | \(\ds \neg ( \neg P \land \neg Q )\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds P \iff Q\) | \(\operatorname{for}\) | \(\ds ( ( P \implies Q ) \land ( Q \implies P ) )\) | justified because $\implies$ is already a definitional abbreviation |
$\implies$ and $\neg$ can be taken as primitive connectives with the following definitional abbreviations:
\(\ds ( P \land Q )\) | \(\operatorname{for}\) | \(\ds \neg ( P \implies \neg Q )\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds ( P \lor Q )\) | \(\operatorname{for}\) | \(\ds ( \neg P \implies Q )\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds ( P \iff Q )\) | \(\operatorname{for}\) | \(\ds \neg ( ( P \implies Q ) \implies \neg ( Q \implies P ) )\) |
The Sheffer stroke $\mid$ can be taken as a sole primitive connective with the following definitional abbreviations:
\(\ds \neg P\) | \(\operatorname{for}\) | \(\ds ( P \mid P )\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds ( P \implies Q )\) | \(\operatorname{for}\) | \(\ds ( P \mid ( Q \mid Q ) )\) |
The other connectives can be defined using $\neg P$ and $( P \implies Q )$ as the "new" primitive connectives.
Quantifiers
The language of set theory adopts the same quantifiers as those in the language of predicate logic.
However, only $\forall$ is necessary to adopt as a primitive symbol, and $\exists$ can be defined:
- $\exists x: P(x) \operatorname{for} \neg \forall x: \neg P(x)$
Rules of Formation
The language of set theory is endowed with the following rules of formation:
- If $x$ and $y$ are variables, then $x \in y$ is a well-formed formula.
- If $P$ and $Q$ are well-formed formulae, then $\neg P$, $( P \implies Q )$, $( P \land Q )$, $( P \lor Q )$, and $( P \iff Q )$ are also well-formed formulae.
- If $P$ is a well-formed formula and $x$ is a variable, then $\forall x: ( P )$ and $\exists x: ( P )$ are well-formed formulae.
It is seen that these rules constitute a bottom-up grammar.
Sources
- 1971: Gaisi Takeuti and Wilson M. Zaring: Introduction to Axiomatic Set Theory: $\S 2$
- 2002: Thomas Jech: Set Theory (3rd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Language of Set Theory, Formulas