Functionally Complete Logical Connectives/Negation and Disjunction
Jump to navigation
Jump to search
Theorem
The set of logical connectives:
![]() | This article is complete as far as it goes, but it could do with expansion. In particular: to adopt the notion of Independent Set of Statements You can help $\mathsf{Pr} \infty \mathsf{fWiki}$ by adding this information. To discuss this page in more detail, feel free to use the talk page. When this work has been completed, you may remove this instance of {{Expand}} from the code.If you would welcome a second opinion as to whether your work is correct, add a call to {{Proofread}} the page. |
Proof
From Functionally Complete Logical Connectives: Negation and Conjunction, $\set {\neg, \land}$ is functionally complete.
That is: any expression can be expressed in terms of $\neg$ and $\land$.
From De Morgan's laws: Conjunction, we have that:
- $p \land q \dashv \vdash \neg \paren {\neg p \lor \neg q}$
Thus all occurrences of $\land$ can be replaced by $\lor$ and $\neg$.
Thus any expression can be expressed in terms of $\neg$ and $\lor$.
That is: $\set {\neg, \lor}$ is functionally complete.
$\blacksquare$
Sources
- 1959: A.H. Basson and D.J. O'Connor: Introduction to Symbolic Logic (3rd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 2.5$: Further Logical Constants
- 1965: E.J. Lemmon: Beginning Logic ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $2$: The Propositional Calculus $2$: $3$ Truth-Tables: Exercise $2 \ \text{(i)}$
- 1972: A.G. Howson: A Handbook of Terms used in Algebra and Analysis ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1$: Some mathematical language: Connectives
- 1982: P.M. Cohn: Algebra Volume 1 (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Sets and mappings: $\S 1.1$: The need for logic
- 2012: M. Ben-Ari: Mathematical Logic for Computer Science (3rd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 2.4.2$: Theorem $2.36$