Thomae Function is Continuous at Irrational Numbers/Lemma
Lemma for Thomae Function is Continuous at Irrational Numbers
In the following it is to be understood that all rational numbers expressed in the form $\dfrac p q$ are in canonical form.
Let $x \in \R \setminus \Q$.
Let $\Q$ be ordered in the following way:
- $\dfrac {p_1} {q_1} \prec \dfrac {p_2} {q_2} \iff \begin {cases} q_1 < q_2 & : q_1 \ne q_2 \\ p_1 < p_2 & : q_1 = q_2 \end {cases}$
and so we can denote $\Q$ with this ordering as $\struct {\Q, \prec}$
Let $q \in \Z_{>0}$ be a positive integer.
Let $S \subseteq \struct {\Q, \prec}$ defined as:
- $S = \set {z \in \Q: z \prec \dfrac 1 q}$
That is, $S$ is the set of all rational numbers whose denominators are all less than or equal to $q$.
Let $a$ be the supremum of the set:
- $\set {z \in S: z < x}$
Let $b$ be the infimum of the set:
- $\set {z \in S: x < z}$
Then we have that the open interval:
- $C = \openint a b$
contains $x$ and no rational numbers whose denominators are less than $q$.
Proof
Let $F := \floor x$ be the floor of $x$.
Let $C := \ceiling x$ be the ceiling of $x$.
Consider the interval:
- $I = \closedint F C$
As $x$ is irrational, we have that:
- $F < x < C$
and so:
- $x \in I$
Because $F$ and $C$ are integers by definition, they can be expressed as:
- $F = \dfrac F 1$
- $C = \dfrac C 1$
and so $F, C \in S$
Let $r \le q$.
Consider the set $S_r$:
- $S_r = \set {F, F + \dfrac 1 r, F + \dfrac 2 r, \ldots, F + \dfrac {r - 1} r, C}$
which is a finite set of rational numbers.
We have that:
- $I = S_1 \cup S_2 \cup S_3 \cup \cdots \cup S_{q - 1} \cup S_q$
and so it follows that $I$ is itself finite.
Then we have that:
\(\ds a = \sup \set {z \in S: z < x}\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \sup \set {z \in I: z < x}\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds b = \inf \set {z \in S: x < z}\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \inf \set {z \in I: x < z}\) |
But as $I$ is finite, then so are $\set {z \in I: z < x}$ and $\set {z \in I: x < z}$.
Because $F \in \set {z \in I: z < x}$ and $C \in \set {z \in I: x < z}$ we have that neither $\set {z \in I: z < x}$ nor $\set {z \in I: x < z}$ are empty.
Hence from Finite Subset of Ordered Set contains Supremum:
- $a \in \set {z \in I: z < x}$
and from Finite Subset of Ordered Set contains Infimum:
- $b \in \set {z \in I: x < z}$
Hence $\exists a, b, \in S: a < x < b$
It follows from the construction that there are no elements of $S$ in \openint a b$.
$\blacksquare$