Compact Hausdorff Topology is Maximally Compact
Theorem
Let $T = \struct {S, \tau}$ be a Hausdorff space which is compact.
Then $\tau$ is maximally compact.
Proof
Let $\tau'$ be a topology on $S$ such that $\tau \subseteq \tau'$ but that $\tau \ne \tau'$.
Consider the identity mapping $I_S: \struct {S, \tau'} \to \struct {S, \tau}$.
From Separation Properties Preserved in Subspace, $I_S$ is a continuous bijection from a Hausdorff space to a compact Hausdorff space.
Aiming for a contradiction, suppose $\struct {S, \tau'}$ is compact.
Then $I_S$ is also open, and so $\tau' \subseteq \tau$.
![]() | This article, or a section of it, needs explaining. In particular: Why does the fact that $\struct {S, \tau'}$ is compact mean $I_S$ is open? You can help $\mathsf{Pr} \infty \mathsf{fWiki}$ by explaining it. To discuss this page in more detail, feel free to use the talk page. When this work has been completed, you may remove this instance of {{Explain}} from the code. |
Thus we have that $\tau \subseteq \tau'$ and $\tau' \subseteq \tau$.
Hence by definition of set equality:
- $\tau' = \tau$
But this contradicts our hypothesis that $\tau' \ne \tau$.
By Proof by Contradiction, it follows that no topology which is strictly finer than $\tau$ can be compact.
$\blacksquare$
Sources
- 1978: Lynn Arthur Steen and J. Arthur Seebach, Jr.: Counterexamples in Topology (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Part $\text I$: Basic Definitions: Section $3$: Compactness: Compactness Properties and the $T_i$ Axioms