Hausdorff Paradox
This article needs to be linked to other articles. You can help $\mathsf{Pr} \infty \mathsf{fWiki}$ by adding these links. To discuss this page in more detail, feel free to use the talk page. When this work has been completed, you may remove this instance of {{MissingLinks}} from the code. |
Theorem
There exists a disjoint decomposition of the sphere $\mathbb S^2$ into four sets $A, B, C, Q$ such that $A, B, C, B \cup C$ are all congruent and $Q$ is countable.
This article, or a section of it, needs explaining. In particular: Jech's analysis implies that the full concept of decomposition may not be necessary. We should be able to get away with just a set partition. You can help $\mathsf{Pr} \infty \mathsf{fWiki}$ by explaining it. To discuss this page in more detail, feel free to use the talk page. When this work has been completed, you may remove this instance of {{Explain}} from the code. |
This page has been identified as a candidate for refactoring of advanced complexity. In particular: In progress. Following the presentation of Jech. Until this has been finished, please leave {{Refactor}} in the code.
New contributors: Refactoring is a task which is expected to be undertaken by experienced editors only. Because of the underlying complexity of the work needed, it is recommended that you do not embark on a refactoring task until you have become familiar with the structural nature of pages of $\mathsf{Pr} \infty \mathsf{fWiki}$.To discuss this page in more detail, feel free to use the talk page. When this work has been completed, you may remove this instance of {{Refactor}} from the code. |
Proof 1
Let $R \subset \map {\mathbb {SO} } 3$ be the group generated by the $\pi$ and $\dfrac {2 \pi} 3$ rotations around different axes.
The elements:
- $\psi = \begin {pmatrix} -\tfrac 1 2 & \tfrac {\sqrt 3} 2 & 0 \\ -\tfrac {\sqrt 3} 2 & -\tfrac 1 2 & 0 \\ 0 & 0 & 1 \\ \end {pmatrix}$
- $\phi = \begin {pmatrix} -\map \cos \vartheta & 0 & \map \sin \vartheta \\ 0 & -1 & 0 \\ \map \sin \vartheta & 0 & \map \cos \vartheta \\ \end {pmatrix}$
form a basis for $R$ for some $\vartheta$.
We have:
- $\psi^3 = \phi^2 = \mathbf I_3$
where $\mathbf I_3$ is the identity mapping in $\mathbb R^3$.
Therefore $\forall r \in R: r \ne \mathbf I_3, \psi, \phi, \psi^2$ there exists some $n \in \N$ and some set of numbers $m_k \in \set {1, 2}, 1 \le k \le n$ such that $r$ can written as one of the following:
- $\text{(a)}: \quad \ds r = \prod_{k \mathop = 1}^n \phi \psi^{m_k}$
- $\text{(b)}: \quad \ds r = \map {\psi^{m_1} } {\prod_{k \mathop = 2}^n \phi \psi^{m_k} }\phi$
- $\text{(c)}: \quad \ds r = \paren {\prod_{k \mathop = 1}^n \phi \psi^{m_k} } \phi$
- $\text{(d)}: \quad \ds r = \map {\psi^{m_1} } {\prod_{k \mathop = 2}^n \phi \psi^{m_k} }$
Now we fix $\vartheta$ such that $\mathbf I_3$ cannot be written in any of the ways $\text{(a)}$, $\text{(b)}$, $\text{(c)}$, $\text{(d)}$.
The action of $R$ on $\mathbb S^2$ will leave two points unchanged for each element of $R$ (the intersection of the axis of rotation and the sphere, to be exact).
Since $R$ is finitely generated, it is a countable group.
Therefore the set of points of $\mathbb S^2$ which are unchanged by at least one element of $R$ is also countable.
We call this set $Q \subset \mathbb S^2$, so that $R$ acts freely on $\mathbb S^2 \setminus Q$.
By Set of Orbits forms Partition, this partitions $\mathbb S^2 \setminus Q$ into orbits.
By the Axiom of Choice, there is a set $X$ containing one element of each orbit.
For any $r \in R$, let $X_r$ be the right action of $r$ on $X$.
We have:
- $\ds \mathbb S^2 \setminus Q = \bigcup_{r \mathop \in R} X_r$
Define the sets $A, B, C$ to be the smallest sets satisfying
- $X \subseteq A$
- If $X_r \subset A, B, C$, then $X_{r\phi} \subset B, A, A$, respectively.
- If $X_r \subset A, B, C$, then $X_{r\psi} \subset B, C, A$, respectively.
- If $X_r \subset A, B, C$, then $X_{r\psi^2} \subset C, A, B$, respectively.
These sets are defined due to the uniqueness of the properties $\text{(a)}$ to $\text{(d)}$
Also, $A, B, C, B \cup C$ are congruent since they are rotations of each other, namely:
- $A_\psi = B, B_{\psi^2} = C, A_\phi = B \cup C$
Hence we have constructed the sets $A, B, C, Q$ of the theorem.
$\blacksquare$
Proof 2
Lemma $1$
Let $G$ be the free product of the groups $G_1 = \set {e_1, \phi}$ and $G_2 = \set {e_2, \psi, \psi^2}$.
Let $U := \mathbb D^3 \subset \R^3$ be a unit ball in real Euclidean space of $3$ dimensions.
Let $\phi$ and $\psi$ be represented by the axes of rotation $a_\phi$ and $a_\psi$ passing through the center of $U$ such that:
- $\phi$ is a rotation by $180 \degrees$, that is $\pi$ radians about $a_\phi$
- $\psi$ is a rotation by $120 \degrees$, that is $\dfrac {2 \pi} 3$ radians about $a_\psi$
Hence consider $G$ as the group of all rotations generated by $\phi$ and $\psi$.
The identity of $G$ is then the identity mapping $\mathbf I_3$.
Then $a_\phi$ and $a_\psi$ can be determined in such a way that distinct elements of $G$ represent distinct rotations generated by $\phi$ and $\psi$.
$\Box$
Lemma $2$
The group $G$ can be partitioned into $3$ disjoint sets:
- $G = A \cup B \cup C$
such that:
\(\text {(1)}: \quad\) | \(\ds A \circ \phi\) | \(=\) | \(\ds B \cup C\) | |||||||||||
\(\text {(2)}: \quad\) | \(\ds A \circ \psi\) | \(=\) | \(\ds B\) | |||||||||||
\(\text {(3)}: \quad\) | \(\ds A \circ \psi^2\) | \(=\) | \(\ds C\) |
$\Box$
Let $Q$ be the set of all fixed points of $\Bbb S^2$ of all rotations $\alpha \in G$.
Each such $\alpha$ has $2$ fixed points.
Hence $Q$ is countable.
The set $\Bbb S^2 \setminus Q$ is a disjoint union of all orbits $P_x$ of $G$:
- $P_x = \set {x \alpha: \alpha \in G}$
By the Axiom of Choice, there exists a set $M$ which contains exactly $1$ element in each $P_x$ where $x \in \Bbb S^2 \setminus Q$.
Let:
\(\ds A\) | \(=\) | \(\ds M \circ \mathscr A\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds B\) | \(=\) | \(\ds M \circ \mathscr B\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds C\) | \(=\) | \(\ds M \circ \mathscr C\) |
It then follows from Lemma $2$ that:
- $A$, $B$ and $C$ are disjoint
- $A$, $B$ and $C$ are congruent to each other
- $B \cup C$ is congruent to each of $A$, $B$ and $C$
and moreover:
- $S = A \cup B \cup C \cup Q$
$\blacksquare$
Axiom of Choice
This theorem depends on the Axiom of Choice.
Because of some of its bewilderingly paradoxical implications, the Axiom of Choice is considered in some mathematical circles to be controversial.
Most mathematicians are convinced of its truth and insist that it should nowadays be generally accepted.
However, others consider its implications so counter-intuitive and nonsensical that they adopt the philosophical position that it cannot be true.
Whether you view this result as a veridical paradox or an antinomy depends your acceptance or otherwise of the Axiom of Choice.
Source of Name
This entry was named for Felix Hausdorff.
Sources
- 1914: Felix Hausdorff: Grundzüge der Mengenlehre
- 1973: Thomas J. Jech: The Axiom of Choice ... (previous) ... (next): $1.$ Introduction: $1.3$ A paradoxical decomposition of the sphere: Theorem $1.1$