Definition:Natural Numbers/Axiomatization
Definition
The natural numbers $\N$ can be axiomatised in the following ways:
Peano's Axioms
Peano's axioms are intended to reflect the intuition behind $\N$, the mapping $s: \N \to \N: \map s n = n + 1$ and $0$ as an element of $\N$.
Let there be given a set $P$, a mapping $s: P \to P$, and a distinguished element $0$.
Historically, the existence of $s$ and the existence of $0$ were considered the first two of Peano's axioms:
\((\text P 1)\) | $:$ | \(\ds 0 \in P \) | $0$ is an element of $P$ | ||||||
\((\text P 2)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall n \in P:\) | \(\ds \map s n \in P \) | For all $n \in P$, its successor $\map s n$ is also in $P$ |
The other three are as follows:
\((\text P 3)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall m, n \in P:\) | \(\ds \map s m = \map s n \implies m = n \) | $s$ is injective | |||||
\((\text P 4)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall n \in P:\) | \(\ds \map s n \ne 0 \) | $0$ is not in the image of $s$ | |||||
\((\text P 5)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall A \subseteq P:\) | \(\ds \paren {0 \in A \land \paren {\forall z \in A: \map s z \in A} } \implies A = P \) | Principle of Mathematical Induction: | |||||
Any subset $A$ of $P$, containing $0$ and | |||||||||
closed under $s$, is equal to $P$ |
Naturally Ordered Semigroup
The concept of a naturally ordered semigroup is intended to capture the behaviour of the natural numbers $\N$, addition $+$ and the ordering $\le$ as they pertain to $\N$.
Naturally Ordered Semigroup Axioms
A naturally ordered semigroup is a (totally) ordered commutative semigroup $\struct {S, \circ, \preceq}$ satisfying:
\((\text {NO} 1)\) | $:$ | $S$ is well-ordered by $\preceq$ | \(\ds \forall T \subseteq S:\) | \(\ds T = \O \lor \exists m \in T: \forall n \in T: m \preceq n \) | |||||
\((\text {NO} 2)\) | $:$ | $\circ$ is cancellable in $S$ | \(\ds \forall m, n, p \in S:\) | \(\ds m \circ p = n \circ p \implies m = n \) | |||||
\(\ds p \circ m = p \circ n \implies m = n \) | |||||||||
\((\text {NO} 3)\) | $:$ | Existence of product | \(\ds \forall m, n \in S:\) | \(\ds m \preceq n \implies \exists p \in S: m \circ p = n \) | |||||
\((\text {NO} 4)\) | $:$ | $S$ has at least two distinct elements | \(\ds \exists m, n \in S:\) | \(\ds m \ne n \) |
1-Based Natural Numbers
The following axioms capture the behaviour of $\N_{>0}$, the element $1 \in \N_{>0}$, and the operations $+$ and $\times$ as they pertain to $\N_{>0}$:
\((\text A)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \exists_1 1 \in \N_{> 0}:\) | \(\ds a \times 1 = a = 1 \times a \) | ||||||
\((\text B)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall a, b \in \N_{> 0}:\) | \(\ds a \times \paren {b + 1} = \paren {a \times b} + a \) | ||||||
\((\text C)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall a, b \in \N_{> 0}:\) | \(\ds a + \paren {b + 1} = \paren {a + b} + 1 \) | ||||||
\((\text D)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall a \in \N_{> 0}, a \ne 1:\) | \(\ds \exists_1 b \in \N_{> 0}: a = b + 1 \) | ||||||
\((\text E)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall a, b \in \N_{> 0}:\) | \(\ds \)Exactly one of these three holds:\( \) | ||||||
\(\ds a = b \lor \paren {\exists x \in \N_{> 0}: a + x = b} \lor \paren {\exists y \in \N_{> 0}: a = b + y} \) | |||||||||
\((\text F)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall A \subseteq \N_{> 0}:\) | \(\ds \paren {1 \in A \land \paren {z \in A \implies z + 1 \in A} } \implies A = \N_{> 0} \) |