Definition:Natural Numbers
This page is about everyday numbers used for counting. For other uses, see Finite Ordinal.
Informal Definition
The natural numbers are the counting numbers.
The set of natural numbers is denoted $\N$:
- $\N = \set {0, 1, 2, 3, \ldots}$
This sequence is A001477 in the On-Line Encyclopedia of Integer Sequences (N. J. A. Sloane (Ed.), 2008).
The set $\N \setminus \set 0$ is denoted $\N_{>0}$:
- $\N_{>0} = \set {1, 2, 3, \ldots}$
This sequence is A000027 in the On-Line Encyclopedia of Integer Sequences (N. J. A. Sloane (Ed.), 2008).
The set of natural numbers is one of the most important sets in mathematics.
Axiomatization
Peano's Axioms
Peano's Axioms are intended to reflect the intuition behind $\N$, the mapping $s: \N \to \N: \map s n = n + 1$ and $0$ as an element of $\N$.
Let there be given a set $P$, a mapping $s: P \to P$, and a distinguished element $0$.
Historically, the existence of $s$ and the existence of $0$ were considered the first two of Peano's Axioms:
\((\text P 1)\) | $:$ | \(\ds 0 \in P \) | $0$ is an element of $P$ | ||||||
\((\text P 2)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall n \in P:\) | \(\ds \map s n \in P \) | For all $n \in P$, its successor $\map s n$ is also in $P$ |
The other three are as follows:
\((\text P 3)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall m, n \in P:\) | \(\ds \map s m = \map s n \implies m = n \) | $s$ is injective | |||||
\((\text P 4)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall n \in P:\) | \(\ds \map s n \ne 0 \) | $0$ is not in the image of $s$ | |||||
\((\text P 5)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall A \subseteq P:\) | \(\ds \paren {0 \in A \land \paren {\forall z \in A: \map s z \in A} } \implies A = P \) | Principle of Mathematical Induction: | |||||
Any subset $A$ of $P$, containing $0$ and | |||||||||
closed under $s$, is equal to $P$ |
Naturally Ordered Semigroup
The concept of a naturally ordered semigroup is intended to capture the behaviour of the natural numbers $\N$, addition $+$ and the ordering $\le$ as they pertain to $\N$.
Naturally Ordered Semigroup Axioms
A naturally ordered semigroup is a (totally) ordered commutative semigroup $\struct {S, \circ, \preceq}$ satisfying:
\((\text {NO} 1)\) | $:$ | $S$ is well-ordered by $\preceq$ | \(\ds \forall T \subseteq S:\) | \(\ds T = \O \lor \exists m \in T: \forall n \in T: m \preceq n \) | |||||
\((\text {NO} 2)\) | $:$ | $\circ$ is cancellable in $S$ | \(\ds \forall m, n, p \in S:\) | \(\ds m \circ p = n \circ p \implies m = n \) | |||||
\(\ds p \circ m = p \circ n \implies m = n \) | |||||||||
\((\text {NO} 3)\) | $:$ | Existence of product | \(\ds \forall m, n \in S:\) | \(\ds m \preceq n \implies \exists p \in S: m \circ p = n \) | |||||
\((\text {NO} 4)\) | $:$ | $S$ has at least two distinct elements | \(\ds \exists m, n \in S:\) | \(\ds m \ne n \) |
1-Based Natural Numbers
The following axioms are intended to capture the behaviour of $\N_{>0}$, the element $1 \in \N_{>0}$, and the operations $+$ and $\times$ as they pertain to $\N_{>0}$:
\((\text A)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \exists_1 1 \in \N_{> 0}:\) | \(\ds a \times 1 = a = 1 \times a \) | ||||||
\((\text B)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall a, b \in \N_{> 0}:\) | \(\ds a \times \paren {b + 1} = \paren {a \times b} + a \) | ||||||
\((\text C)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall a, b \in \N_{> 0}:\) | \(\ds a + \paren {b + 1} = \paren {a + b} + 1 \) | ||||||
\((\text D)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall a \in \N_{> 0}, a \ne 1:\) | \(\ds \exists_1 b \in \N_{> 0}: a = b + 1 \) | ||||||
\((\text E)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall a, b \in \N_{> 0}:\) | \(\ds \)Exactly one of these three holds:\( \) | ||||||
\(\ds a = b \lor \paren {\exists x \in \N_{> 0}: a + x = b} \lor \paren {\exists y \in \N_{> 0}: a = b + y} \) | |||||||||
\((\text F)\) | $:$ | \(\ds \forall A \subseteq \N_{> 0}:\) | \(\ds \paren {1 \in A \land \paren {z \in A \implies z + 1 \in A} } \implies A = \N_{> 0} \) |
Construction
Von Neumann Construction of Natural Numbers
Let $\omega$ denote the minimally inductive set.
The natural numbers can be defined as the elements of $\omega$.
Following Definition 2 of $\omega$, this amounts to defining the natural numbers as the finite ordinals.
In terms of the empty set $\O$ and successor sets, we thus define:
\(\ds 0\) | \(:=\) | \(\ds \O = \set {}\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds 1\) | \(:=\) | \(\ds 0^+ = 0 \cup \set 0 = \set 0\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds 2\) | \(:=\) | \(\ds 1^+ = 1 \cup \set 1 = \set {0, 1}\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds 3\) | \(:=\) | \(\ds 2^+ = 2 \cup \set 2 = \set {0, 1, 2}\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds \) | \(\vdots\) | \(\ds \) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds n + 1\) | \(:=\) | \(\ds n^+ = n \cup \set n\) |
Inductive Set Definition for Natural Numbers
Let $x$ be a set which is an element of every inductive set.
Then $x$ is a natural number.
Inductive Set Definition for Natural Numbers in Real Numbers
Let $\R$ be the set of real numbers.
Let $\II$ be the set of all inductive sets defined as subsets of $\R$.
Then the natural numbers $\N$ are defined as:
- $\N := \ds \bigcap \II$
where $\ds \bigcap$ denotes intersection.
Notation
Some sources use a different style of letter from $\N$: you will find $N$, $\mathbf N$, etc. However, $\N$ is commonplace and all but universal.
The usual symbol for denoting $\set {1, 2, 3, \ldots}$ is $\N^*$, but the more explicit $\N_{>0}$ is standard on $\mathsf{Pr} \infty \mathsf{fWiki}$.
Some authors refer to $\set {0, 1, 2, 3, \ldots}$ as $\tilde \N$, and refer to $\set {1, 2, 3, \ldots}$ as $\N$.
Either is valid, and as long as it is clear which is which, it does not matter which is used. However, using $\N = \set {0, 1, 2, 3, \ldots}$ is a more modern approach, particularly in the field of computer science, where starting the count at zero is usual.
Treatments which consider the natural numbers as $\set {1, 2, 3, \ldots}$ sometimes refer to $\set {0, 1, 2, 3, \ldots}$ as the positive (or non-negative) integers $\Z_{\ge 0}$.
The following notations are sometimes used:
- $\N_0 = \set {0, 1, 2, 3, \ldots}$
- $\N_1 = \set {1, 2, 3, \ldots}$
However, beware of confusing this notation with the use of $\N_n$ as the initial segment of the natural numbers:
- $\N_n = \set {0, 1, 2, \ldots, n - 1}$
under which notational convention $\N_0 = \O$ and $\N_1 = \set 0$.
So it is important to ensure that it is understood exactly which convention is being used.
The use of $\N$ or its variants is not universal, either.
Some sources, for example Nathan Jacobson: Lectures in Abstract Algebra: Volume $\text { I }$: Basic Concepts ($1951$) uses $P = \set {1, 2, 3, \ldots}$.
This may stem from the fact that Jacobson's presentation starts with Peano's axioms.
On the other hand, it may just be because $P$ is the first letter of positive.
Similarly, Undergraduate Topology by Robert H. Kasriel uses $\mathbf P$, which he describes as the set of all positive integers.
Based on defining $\N$ as being the minimally inductive set $\omega$, 1960: Paul R. Halmos: Naive Set Theory suggests using $\omega$ for the set of natural numbers.
This convention is followed by Raymond M. Smullyan and Melvin Fitting in their Set Theory and the Continuum Problem.
This use of $\omega$ is usually seen for the order type of the natural numbers, that is, $\struct {\N, \le}$ where $\le$ is the usual ordering on the natural numbers.
Also known as
The natural numbers are also known as counting numbers, especially in elementary school.
The term proper number can sometimes be seen in popular literature.
Also see
- Results about natural numbers as an abstract algebraical concept can be found here.
Historical Note
The natural numbers were the first numbers to be considered.
Their earliest use was in the sense of ordinal numbers, when they were used for counting.
The origin of the name natural numbers (considered by some authors to be a misnomer) originates with the Ancient Greeks, for whom the only numbers were the strictly positive integers $1, 2, 3, \ldots$
It is customary at this stage to quote the famous epigram of Leopold Kronecker, translated from the German in various styles, for example:
- God created the natural numbers, and all the rest is the work of man.
Linguistic Note
The words for the individual natural numbers in ancient languages which have now been supplanted by newer ones have in some cases survived in remote places for special purposes.
The traditional system of numbers used for counting sheep in certain locales in the British Isles is one example:
There are a number of traditional system of numbers used for counting sheep in certain locales in the British Isles.
This is one example:
\((1)\) | $:$ | wan | |||||||
\((2)\) | $:$ | twan | |||||||
\((3)\) | $:$ | tethera | |||||||
\((4)\) | $:$ | methera | |||||||
\((5)\) | $:$ | pimp | |||||||
\((6)\) | $:$ | sethera | |||||||
\((7)\) | $:$ | lethera | |||||||
\((8)\) | $:$ | hovera | |||||||
\((9)\) | $:$ | dovera | |||||||
\((10)\) | $:$ | dick | |||||||
\((11)\) | $:$ | wanadick | |||||||
\((12)\) | $:$ | twanadick | |||||||
\((13)\) | $:$ | tetheradick | |||||||
\((14)\) | $:$ | metheradick | |||||||
\((15)\) | $:$ | pimpdick | |||||||
\((16)\) | $:$ | setheradick | |||||||
\((17)\) | $:$ | letheradick | |||||||
\((18)\) | $:$ | hoveradick | |||||||
\((19)\) | $:$ | doveradick | |||||||
\((20)\) | $:$ | bumfit | |||||||
\((21)\) | $:$ | wanabumfit |
and so on.
Sources
- 1937: Richard Courant: Differential and Integral Calculus: Volume $\text { I }$ (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $\text I$: Introduction: $1$. The Continuum of Numbers
- 1939: E.G. Phillips: A Course of Analysis (2nd ed.) ... (next): Chapter $\text {I}$: Number: $1.1$ Introduction
- 1951: Nathan Jacobson: Lectures in Abstract Algebra: Volume $\text { I }$: Basic Concepts ... (previous) ... (next): Introduction $\S 4$: The natural numbers
- 1960: Walter Ledermann: Complex Numbers ... (next): $\S 1.1$. Number Systems
- 1964: W.E. Deskins: Abstract Algebra ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 2.1$
- 1964: Steven A. Gaal: Point Set Topology ... (previous) ... (next): Introduction to Set Theory: $1$. Elementary Operations on Sets
- 1964: J. Hunter: Number Theory ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $\text {I}$: Number Systems and Algebraic Structures: $1$. Introduction
- 1965: Seth Warner: Modern Algebra ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $\text I$: Algebraic Structures: $\S 1$: The Language of Set Theory
- 1971: Allan Clark: Elements of Abstract Algebra ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Mappings: $\S 15$
- 1971: Robert H. Kasriel: Undergraduate Topology ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1.8$: Collections of Sets: Definition $8.4$
- 1972: A.G. Howson: A Handbook of Terms used in Algebra and Analysis ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 4$: Number systems $\text{I}$
- 1974: Murray R. Spiegel: Theory and Problems of Advanced Calculus (SI ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Numbers: Real Numbers: $1$
- 1975: T.S. Blyth: Set Theory and Abstract Algebra ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1$. Sets; inclusion; intersection; union; complementation; number systems
- 1975: Bert Mendelson: Introduction to Topology (3rd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Theory of Sets: $\S 1$: Introduction
- 1975: W.A. Sutherland: Introduction to Metric and Topological Spaces ... (previous) ... (next): Notation and Terminology
- 1977: K.G. Binmore: Mathematical Analysis: A Straightforward Approach ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1$: Real Numbers: $\S 1.2$: The set of real numbers
- 1978: Thomas A. Whitelaw: An Introduction to Abstract Algebra ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 2$: Introductory remarks on sets: $\text{(b)}$
- 1980: David M. Burton: Elementary Number Theory (revised ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Some Preliminary Considerations: $1.1$ Mathematical Induction
- 1981: Murray R. Spiegel: Theory and Problems of Complex Variables (SI ed.) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Complex Numbers: The Real Number System: $1$
- 1982: P.M. Cohn: Algebra Volume 1 (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $2$: Integers and natural numbers: $\S 2.1$: The integers
- 1982: Alan G. Hamilton: Numbers, Sets and Axioms ... (next): $\S 1$: Numbers: $1.1$ Natural Numbers and Integers
- 1989: George S. Boolos and Richard C. Jeffrey: Computability and Logic (3rd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $1$ Enumerability
- 1994: H.E. Rose: A Course in Number Theory (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $1$ Divisibility: $1.1$ The Euclidean algorithm and unique factorization
- 1996: H. Jerome Keisler and Joel Robbin: Mathematical Logic and Computability ... (previous) ... (next): Appendix $\text A$: Sets and Functions: $\text{A}.1$: Sets
- 1998: David Nelson: The Penguin Dictionary of Mathematics (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): counting number
- 1998: David Nelson: The Penguin Dictionary of Mathematics (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): natural number
- 1998: David Nelson: The Penguin Dictionary of Mathematics (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): number: 1. (natural number)
- 1999: András Hajnal and Peter Hamburger: Set Theory ... (previous) ... (next): $1$. Notation, Conventions: $2$
- 2000: Michael R.A. Huth and Mark D. Ryan: Logic in Computer Science: Modelling and reasoning about systems ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1.2.5$: An aside: proof by contradiction
- 2008: David Joyner: Adventures in Group Theory (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $2$: 'And you do addition?': $\S 2.1$: Functions: Example $2.1.1$
- 2008: David Nelson: The Penguin Dictionary of Mathematics (4th ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): counting number
- 2008: David Nelson: The Penguin Dictionary of Mathematics (4th ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): natural number
- 2008: David Nelson: The Penguin Dictionary of Mathematics (4th ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): number: 1. (natural number)
- 2008: Ian Stewart: Taming the Infinite ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $2$: The Logic of Shape: Pythagoras
- 2008: Ian Stewart: Taming the Infinite ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $3$: Notations and Numbers: Negative numbers
- 2010: Raymond M. Smullyan and Melvin Fitting: Set Theory and the Continuum Problem (revised ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: General Background: $\S 1$ What is infinity?
- 2010: Raymond M. Smullyan and Melvin Fitting: Set Theory and the Continuum Problem (revised ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: General Background: $\S 5$ The continuum problem
- 2014: Christopher Clapham and James Nicholson: The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Mathematics (5th ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): counting numbers
- 2014: Christopher Clapham and James Nicholson: The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Mathematics (5th ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): natural number