Definition:Conditional
Definition
The conditional is a binary connective:
- $p \implies q$
defined as:
- If $p$ is true, then $q$ is true.
This is known as a conditional statement.
$p \implies q$ is voiced:
- if $p$ then $q$
or:
- $p$ implies $q$
We are at liberty to write this the other way round. $q \impliedby p$ means the same as $p \implies q$.
$q \impliedby p$ is sometimes known as a reverse implication.
The rest of this article interprets the conditional in its usual mathematical sense.
That is, $p \implies q$ is considered to be true whenever:
- $p$ is false
or:
- $q$ is true.
This interpretation of a conditional is called logical implication or material implication.
Its most important property is that the truth of $p \implies q$ does not a priori establish a relation of causality between $p$ and $q$.
This allows for the conditional to be truth-functional, at the price of a slight mismatch with its use in natural language.
Truth Function
The conditional connective defines the truth function $f^\to$ as follows:
\(\ds \map {f^\to} {\F, \F}\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \T\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds \map {f^\to} {\F, \T}\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \T\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds \map {f^\to} {\T, \F}\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \F\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds \map {f^\to} {\T, \T}\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \T\) |
Truth Table
The characteristic truth table of the conditional (implication) operator $p \implies q$ is as follows:
- $\begin {array} {|cc||c|} \hline p & q & p \implies q \\ \hline \F & \F & \T \\ \F & \T & \T \\ \T & \F & \F \\ \T & \T & \T \\ \hline \end {array}$
Boolean Interpretation
The truth value of $\mathbf A \implies \mathbf B$ under a boolean interpretation $v$ is given by:
- $\map v {\mathbf A \implies \mathbf B} = \begin{cases} \T & : \map v {\mathbf A} = \F \text{ or } \map v {\mathbf B} = \T \\ \F & : \text{otherwise} \end{cases}$
and the truth value of $\mathbf A \impliedby \mathbf B$ under a boolean interpretation $v$ is given by:
- $\map v {\mathbf A \impliedby \mathbf B} = \begin{cases} \T & : \map v {\mathbf A} = \T \text{ or } \map v {\mathbf B} = \F \\ \F & : \text{otherwise} \end{cases}$
Semantics of the Conditional
$p \implies q$ can be stated thus:
- If $p$ is true then $q$ is true.
- $q$ is true if $p$ is true.
- (The truth of) $p$ implies (the truth of) $q$.
- (The truth of) $q$ is implied by (the truth of) $p$.
- $q$ follows from $p$.
- $p$ is true only if $q$ is true.
The latter one may need some explanation. $p$ can be either true or false, as can $q$. But if $q$ is false, and $p \implies q$, then $p$ can not be true. Therefore, $p$ can be true only if $q$ is also true, which leads us to our assertion.
- $p$ is true therefore $q$ is true.
- $p$ is true entails that $q$ is true.
- $q$ is true because $p$ is true.
- $p$ may be true unless $q$ is false.
- Given that $p$ is true, $q$ is true.
- $q$ is true whenever $p$ is true.
- $q$ is true provided that $p$ is true.
- $q$ is true in case $p$ is true.
- $q$ is true assuming that $p$ is true.
- $q$ is true on the condition that $p$ is true.
Language of the Conditional
The conditional has been discussed at great length throughout the ages, and a whole language has evolved around it. For now, here are a few definitions:
Weak
In a conditional $p \implies q$, the statement $q$ is weaker than $p$.
Strong
In a conditional $p \implies q$, the statement $p$ is stronger than $q$.
Thus we have the notion of certain theorems having a weak and a strong version.
Superimplicant
In a conditional $p \implies q$, the statement $p$ is superimplicant to $q$.
Subimplicant
In a conditional $p \implies q$, the statement $q$ is subimplicant to $p$.
Antecedent
In a conditional $p \implies q$, the statement $p$ is the antecedent.
Consequent
In a conditional $p \implies q$, the statement $q$ is the consequent.
Necessary Condition
Let $p \implies q$ be a conditional statement.
Then $q$ is a necessary condition for $p$.
That is, if $p \implies q$, then it is necessary that $q$ be true for $p$ to be true.
This is because unless $q$ is true, $p$ cannot be true.
Sufficient Condition
Let $p \implies q$ be a conditional statement.
Then $p$ is a sufficient condition for $q$.
That is, if $p \implies q$, then for $q$ to be true, it is sufficient to know that $p$ is true.
This is because of the fact that if you know that $p$ is true, you know enough to know also that $q$ is true.
Fallacies Concerning the Conditional
If we know that $q$ is true, and that $p \implies q$, this tells us nothing about the truth value of $p$. This also takes some thinking about. Here is a plausible example which may illustrate this.
Let $P$ be the statement:
- $x$ is a whole number divisible by $4$.
Let $Q$ be the statement:
- $x$ is an even whole number.
It is straightforward to prove the implication $P \implies Q$. (We see that if $P$ is true, that is, that $x$ is a whole number divisible by $4$, then $x$ must be an even whole number, so $Q$ is true.) However, $Q$ can quite possibly be an even number that is not divisible by $4$, for example, $x = 6$. In this case, $Q$ is true, but $P$ is false.
To suppose otherwise is to commit a fallacy. So common are the fallacies that may be committed with regard to the conditional that they have been given names of their own:
Affirming the Consequent
Let $p \implies q$ be a conditional statement.
Let its consequent $q$ be true.
Then it is a fallacy to assert that the antecedent $p$ is also necessarily true.
That is:
\(\ds p\) | \(\implies\) | \(\ds q\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds q\) | \(\) | \(\ds \) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds \not \vdash \ \ \) | \(\ds p\) | \(\) | \(\ds \) |
This fallacy is called affirming the consequent.
Denying the Antecedent
Let $p \implies q$ be a conditional statement.
Let its antecedent $p$ be false.
Then it is a fallacy to assert that the consequent $q$ is also necessarily false.
That is:
\(\ds p\) | \(\implies\) | \(\ds q\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds \neg p\) | \(\) | \(\ds \) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds \not \vdash \ \ \) | \(\ds \neg q\) | \(\) | \(\ds \) |
This fallacy is called denying the antecedent.
Formal Implication
Formal implication is a usage of an implication in which it is necessary for there to be a formal connection between the antecedent and the consequent in order for the implication to have any semantic meaning.
Further Definitions
Converse
The converse of the conditional:
- $p \implies q$
is the statement:
- $q \implies p$
Inverse
The inverse of the conditional:
- $p \implies q$
is the statement:
- $\neg p \implies \neg q$
Contrapositive
The contrapositive of the conditional:
- $p \implies q$
is the statement:
- $\neg q \implies \neg p$
Notational Variants
Various symbols are encountered that denote the concept of the conditional:
Symbol | Origin | Known as |
---|---|---|
$p \implies q$ | Implies | |
$p \to q$ | often used when space is limited | |
$p \supset q$ | 1910: Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell: Principia Mathematica | hook or horseshoe |
$p \, \mathop {-\!\!\!<} q$ | Charles Sanders Peirce | sign of illation |
$\operatorname C p q$ | Łukasiewicz's Polish notation |
In mathematics, as opposed to works concerned purely with logic, it is usual to use "$\implies$", as then it can be ensured that it is understood to mean exactly the same thing when we use it in the "mathematical" context. There are other uses in mathematics for the other symbols.
Also known as
A conditional is also known as:
- a conditional statement
- a conditional sentence
- a conditional proposition
- a hypothetical
- an implication
- an implicative statement
- a logical implication
- a material implication.
Also see
- Results about the conditional operator can be found here.
Sources
- 1946: Alfred Tarski: Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of Deductive Sciences (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $\S \text{II}.8$: Implication or Conditional Sentence
- 1959: A.H. Basson and D.J. O'Connor: Introduction to Symbolic Logic (3rd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 2.3$: Basic Truth-Tables of the Propositional Calculus
- 1960: Paul R. Halmos: Naive Set Theory ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 2$: The Axiom of Specification
- 1961: David V. Widder: Advanced Calculus (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $1$ Partial Differentiation: $\S 2$. Functions of One Variable: $2.1$ Limits and Continuity
- 1963: George F. Simmons: Introduction to Topology and Modern Analysis ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1$: Sets and Set Inclusion
- 1964: Donald Kalish and Richard Montague: Logic: Techniques of Formal Reasoning ... (previous) ... (next): $\text{I}$: 'NOT' and 'IF': $\S 1$
- 1964: William K. Smith: Limits and Continuity ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 2.1$: Sets
- 1965: Claude Berge and A. Ghouila-Houri: Programming, Games and Transportation Networks ... (previous) ... (next): $1$. Preliminary ideas; sets, vector spaces: $1.1$. Sets
- 1965: J.A. Green: Sets and Groups ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1.2$. Subsets
- 1965: E.J. Lemmon: Beginning Logic ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: The Propositional Calculus $1$: $2$ Conditionals and Negation
- 1967: George McCarty: Topology: An Introduction with Application to Topological Groups ... (previous) ... (next): Introduction: Logic
- 1970: Arne Broman: Introduction to Partial Differential Equations ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Fourier Series: $1.1$ Basic Concepts: $1.1.2$ Definitions
- 1971: Robert H. Kasriel: Undergraduate Topology ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Sets, Functions, and Relations: $\S 2$: Some Remarks on the Use of the Connectives and, or, implies
- 1972: A.G. Howson: A Handbook of Terms used in Algebra and Analysis ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1$: Some mathematical language: Connectives
- 1972: Patrick Suppes: Axiomatic Set Theory (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1.2$ Logic and Notation
- 1973: Irving M. Copi: Symbolic Logic (4th ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $2$ Arguments Containing Compound Statements: $2.2$: Conditional Statements
- 1975: T.S. Blyth: Set Theory and Abstract Algebra ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1$. Sets; inclusion; intersection; union; complementation; number systems
- 1975: W.A. Sutherland: Introduction to Metric and Topological Spaces ... (next): Notation and Terminology
- 1977: Gary Chartrand: Introductory Graph Theory ... (previous) ... (next): Appendix $\text{A}.5$: Theorems and Proofs
- 1978: Thomas A. Whitelaw: An Introduction to Abstract Algebra ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 4$: The implies sign ($\Rightarrow$)
- 1979: G.H. Hardy and E.M. Wright: An Introduction to the Theory of Numbers (5th ed.) ... (next): Remarks on Notation
- 1980: D.J. O'Connor and Betty Powell: Elementary Logic ... (previous) ... (next): $\S \text{I}: 2$: Logical Constants $(1)$
- 1982: P.M. Cohn: Algebra Volume 1 (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Sets and mappings: $\S 1.1$: The need for logic
- 1988: Alan G. Hamilton: Logic for Mathematicians (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1$: Informal statement calculus: $\S 1.1$: Statements and connectives
- 1993: M. Ben-Ari: Mathematical Logic for Computer Science ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $2$: Propositional Calculus: $\S 2.1$: Boolean operators
- 1993: Keith Devlin: The Joy of Sets: Fundamentals of Contemporary Set Theory (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1$: Naive Set Theory: $\S 1.1$: What is a Set?
- 1996: H. Jerome Keisler and Joel Robbin: Mathematical Logic and Computability ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1.1$: Introduction
- 1998: David Nelson: The Penguin Dictionary of Mathematics (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): conditional
- 1998: David Nelson: The Penguin Dictionary of Mathematics (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): implication: 1. (material implication)
- 1999: András Hajnal and Peter Hamburger: Set Theory ... (previous) ... (next): $1$. Notation, Conventions
- 2000: Michael R.A. Huth and Mark D. Ryan: Logic in Computer Science: Modelling and reasoning about systems ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 1.1$: Declarative sentences
- 2000: James R. Munkres: Topology (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $1$: Set Theory and Logic: $\S 1$: Fundamental Concepts
- 2008: David Joyner: Adventures in Group Theory (2nd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: Elementary, my dear Watson: $\S 1.1$: You have a logical mind if...
- 2008: David Nelson: The Penguin Dictionary of Mathematics (4th ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): conditional
- 2008: David Nelson: The Penguin Dictionary of Mathematics (4th ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): implication: 1. (material implication)
- 2010: Raymond M. Smullyan and Melvin Fitting: Set Theory and the Continuum Problem (revised ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: General Background: $\S 6$ Significance of the results
- 2012: M. Ben-Ari: Mathematical Logic for Computer Science (3rd ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 2.2.3$
- 2014: Christopher Clapham and James Nicholson: The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Mathematics (5th ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): conditional
- 2014: Christopher Clapham and James Nicholson: The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Mathematics (5th ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): implication